Neuroethics and Social Justice
By Neil Levy
![]() |
Image courtesy of Pixabay |
Neuroethics has been especially concerned with cognitive and affective enhancement. A number of enhancement technologies are either in development or already available, including psychopharmaceuticals like methylphenidate (Elliott et al. 1997; Mehta et al. 2000) and modafinil (Turner et al. 2003), and also transcranial direct current stimulation (Kadosh et al. 2010), to name only the most prominent. Many ethicists are deeply worried about these developments. A range of arguments have been advanced purporting to show that the use of cognitive enhancements is impermissible or at least inadvisable.
Some ethicists have attempted to show that alterations produced by psychopharmaceuticals or electrical stimulation of the brain would be inauthentic (e.g. Elliott 1998). Others have focused not on the traits and capacities produced but on the means whereby they are produced: because these means are technological, they risk mechanizing our self-conceptions (Freedman 1998). Yet others have worried that cognitive enhancement might constitute cheating (Schermer 2008). Perhaps most pervasively, ethicists have worried about the social justice implications of cognitive enhancement (Sandel 2009); cognitive enhancement may well prove expensive, limiting access to those who are better off than average. Even if they are relatively cheap, they will almost certainly be out of reach of the roughly 10% of the world’s population living on less than US$2 a day, adjusted for purchasing power (World Bank 2015). Given that these enhancements are likely to be much more available to those who are already better off, they are likely to increase inequality, within and between countries.
Some ethicists have attempted to show that alterations produced by psychopharmaceuticals or electrical stimulation of the brain would be inauthentic (e.g. Elliott 1998). Others have focused not on the traits and capacities produced but on the means whereby they are produced: because these means are technological, they risk mechanizing our self-conceptions (Freedman 1998). Yet others have worried that cognitive enhancement might constitute cheating (Schermer 2008). Perhaps most pervasively, ethicists have worried about the social justice implications of cognitive enhancement (Sandel 2009); cognitive enhancement may well prove expensive, limiting access to those who are better off than average. Even if they are relatively cheap, they will almost certainly be out of reach of the roughly 10% of the world’s population living on less than US$2 a day, adjusted for purchasing power (World Bank 2015). Given that these enhancements are likely to be much more available to those who are already better off, they are likely to increase inequality, within and between countries.
![]() |
Iodine pills. Image courtesy to Mr. Granger, Wikimedia Commons |
Faced with the apparent similarities between uses of cognitive enhancers and cases like iodine supplementation, ethicists have sought to identify relevant differences between the two kinds of cases that would explain and justify differential responses to them. Such responses directly or indirectly turn on two major issues: the distinction between treatment and enhancement, and how natural the intervention is.
The treatment/enhancement distinction rests on distinguishing between states of human beings that fall within the normal range and those that are deficits compared to normal functioning. Roughly, treatments aim to raise people to normal functioning, whereas enhancements aim to raise them above that standard. Many ethicists believe that treatments have a different moral status to enhancements: they are, at minimum, morally more urgent than enhancements (e.g. Daniels 2000). This distinction might be invoked to argue why supplementation with iodine is a morally permissible or even required treatment, while using modafinil or methylphenidate, when not medically indicated, is a morally impermissible enhancement.
![]() |
Image courtesy of Pixabay |
![]() |
Image courtesy of Toby Hudson, Wikimedia Commons |
I am sympathetic to the concern that cognitive enhancements risk increasing existing inequalities. However, I believe that this worry should motivate concern about existing inequalities, not just future possibilities. Environmental enrichment, for instance, is already unequally distributed, and causes predictable differences in cognitive capacity. Contemporary neuroscience is accumulating evidence that even within developed counties, socioeconomic status causes differences in intelligence and cognitive control (Noble, McCandliss & Farah 2007; Hackman, Farah & Meaney 2010). Much of these differences are due to differences in parenting and in the amount of stimulation given to infants (Farah et al. 2008). Nutrition is likely also to play an important role. Even excluding genuine malnutrition, birth-weight, which reflects the nutritional and health status of the mother, is correlated with IQ (Matte et al. 2001). The factors which cause and predict better cognitive capacity, from education to access to books and stimulating environment, better food and less stress, are today unequally distributed within countries. Across countries, the disparities are even starker.
I suggest that the lack of relevant differences between controversial cognitive enhancers and generally accepted environmental interventions ought to motivate a concern with the latter. Consistency requires that we extend our concern to the uneven distribution of the resources that explain, in significant part, why cognitive capacity is predicted by socioeconomic status. If neuroethics is concerned with the ethical issues of how we manipulate our cognitive capacities, at least in part, we can call the broader issue a neuroethical one. It is, I suggest, by far the most urgent neuroethical issue confronting us today. Far more attention should be paid to it, even if that comes at the expense of superficially more exciting problems concerning psychopharmaceuticals.
Insofar as neuroethicists are concerned with the distribution of cognitive capacities, they are and ought to be concerned with social injustice in a broad sense. Poverty, relative and absolute, explains the unequal distribution of cognitive capacities in the world today. It is a far more pressing neuroethical concern than worries about new technologies or new drugs. It is one that ought to motivate all medical professionals, and especially those involved in the frontline provision of medical services.
________________

References
- Daniels, N. (2000). Normal functioning and the treatment-enhancement distinction. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 9, 309-322.
- Dickens, W. T., & Flynn, J. R. (2002). The IQ Paradox Is Still Resolved. Psychological Review 109, 764-771.
- Durga, J., van Boxtel, M. P., Schouten, E. G., et al. (2007). Effect of 3-year folic acid supplementation on cognitive function in older adults in the FACIT trial: a randomised, double blind, controlled trial. Lancet 369(9557), 208–16.
- Elliott, C. (1998). The Tyranny of Happiness: Ethics and Cosmetic Psychopharmacology. In Erik Parens (ed) Enhancing Human Traits: Ethical and Social Implications. Washington, D.C.: Georgetown University Press: 177-188.
- Elliott, R., Sahakian, B. J., Matthews, K., Bannerjea, A., Rimmer, J., & Robbins, T. W. (1997). Effects of methylphenidate on spatial working memory and planning in healthy young adults. Psychopharmacology 131, 196–206.
- Farah, M. J., Betancourt, L., Shera, D. M., Savage, J. H., Giannetta, J. M., Brodsky, N. L., Elsa, K., Malmud, E. K., & Hurt, H. (2008). Environmental stimulation, parental nurturance and cognitive development in humans. Developmental Science 15, 793-801.
- Freedman, C. (1998). Aspirin for the Mind? Some Ethical Worries about Psychopharmacology. In Erik Parens (ed) Enhancing Human Traits: Ethical and Social Implications. Washington, D.C.: Georgetown University Press: 135-150.
- Hackman, D. A., Farah, M. J. & Meaney, M. J. (2010). Socioeconomic status and the brain: Mechanistic insights from human and animal research. Nature Reviews Neuroscience 11, 651-659.
- Kadosh, R. C., Soskic, S., Iuculano, T., Kanal, R., & Walsh, V. (2010). Modulating Neuronal Activity Produces Specific and Long-Lasting Changes in Numerical Competence. Current Biology 20, 2016-2020.
- Matte, T. D., Bresnahan, M., Begg, M. D., & Susser, E. (2001). Influence of variation in birth weight within normal range and within sibships on IQ at age 7 years: cohort study. BMJ 323, 310-314.
- Mehta, M. A., Owen, A. M., Sahakian, B. J., et al. (2000). Methylphenidate enhances working memory by modulating discrete frontal and parietal lobe regions in the human brain. Journal of Neuroscience 20, 65.
- Noble, K. G., McCandliss, B. D., & Farah, M. J. (2007). Socioeconomic gradients predict individual differences in neurocognitive abilities. Developmental Science 10, 464-80.
- Sandel, MJ. (2009). The Case Against Perfection: What’s Wrong with Designer Children, Bionic Athletes, and Genetic Engineering. In J. Savulescu and N. Bostrom (eds) Human Enhancement. Oxford: Oxford University Press: 71-89.
- Schermer, M. (2008). On the argument that enhancement is “cheating”. Journal of Medical Ethics 34, pp. 85-88.
- Turner, D. C., Robbins, T. W., Clark, L., et al. (2003). Cognitive enhancing effects of modafinil in healthy volunteers. Psychopharmacology 165, 260-9.
- UNICEF (2018). Micronutrients – Iodine, Iron and Vitamin A. UNICEF. < http://www.unicef.org/nutrition/index_iodine.html >
- World Bank Development Indicators. < http://wdi.worldbank.org/table/1.2.2 >
- Zimmerman, M. B. (2009). Iodine Deficiency. Endocrine Reviews 30, 376-408.
Levy, N. (2019). Neuroethics and Social Justice. The Neuroethics Blog. Retrieved on , from http://www.theneuroethicsblog.com/2019/04/neuroethics-and-social-justice.html