The Ethics of Dream Recording
By Abi Grassler
![]() |
Image courtesy to PublicDomainPictures |
In the Gallant lab, at the University of California at Berkley, researchers have developed “The Brain Viewer,” a technology that reconstructs images based on neural activity after viewers watched cropped and magnified samples from a screen showing high-resolution films. Right now, reconstructions of faces are low resolution, such that vague outlines of a person can be recognized, and reconstructions of objects or animals are even lower, appearing as blurry patches (Nishimoto et al., 2011). As the research progresses, lab members hope to eventually reconstruct memories and even dreams. Members of the Gallant lab believe this technology can eventually be applied to dreams because both memory reconstruction and dream reconstruction are visually dynamic, meaning there is constant change in perception and neural activity during these processes (Nishimoto et al., 2011). The emergence of such technology raises the possibility of several neuroethical dilemmas, such as privacy and informed consent if these experiments were to eventually be performed in participants in a non-waking state of consciousness.
![]() |
Image courtesy to Lorenza Walker |
During REM sleep, there is usually little control over what we dream about, as dreams are usually a result of spontaneous thought rather than deliberate processing (Windt and Voss, 2018). While a healthy participant is able to give informed consent prior to the start of the recording, once the participant has fallen asleep they would be unable to communicate with others during the recording and would no longer have control over what the researchers conducting the procedure can access or observe. Continued informed consent would be difficult to maintain, which will become more important as technology advances and more personal information could potentially be analyzed from the neural recordings.
With this technology also comes unprecedented privacy concerns. Although the reason why we dream is unclear, some researchers theorize that dreams may be a mechanism to process emotional events, or they may be an abstraction of one’s psychological state (Lemonick, 2004). If these theories are correct, dream recordings would carry highly personal information that could greatly impact an individual’s life, if shared with third parties. If similar to other forms of neuroimaging data, an analysis of one’s dream activity could impact their career, insurance policy, or personal relationships, depending on what could be constructed about their daily life or personality characteristics using the neural activity recordings (Farah, 2015). Recordings could potentially be used in a court setting if this technology is seen as beneficial in determining a suspect’s intent, or to determine whether a witness or suspect is fit to stand trial based on their psychological state.
![]() |
Fuseli, Henry. The Nightmare. c. 1781. Detroit Institute of Art, Detroit. |
________________
I am a senior at Emory double majoring in neuroscience and behavioral biology and dance and movement studies. After graduating this spring, I plan on participating in a post-baccalaureate program and applying to MD/PhD programs.
References
Chow, H., Horovitz, S., Carr, W., Picchioni, D., Coddington, N., Fukunaga, M., . . . Braun, A. (2013). Rhythmic alternating patterns of brain activity distinguish rapid eye movement sleep from other states of consciousness. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences,110(32), 13228-13228. doi:10.1073/pnas.1313191110
Farah, M. (2015). An Ethics Toolbox for Neurotechnology. Neuron,86(1), 34-37. doi:10.1016/j.neuron.2015.03.038
Koch, C. (2018). What Is Consciousness? Nature,557, S9-S12.
Kookoolis, A., Pace-Schott, E. F., & Mcnamara, P. (2010). Dream content and memory processing: Dream lag effects within a single night and across several nights: A pilot study. Dreaming,20(3), 211-217. doi:10.1037/a0020640
Jacobson, H. (2014). Phenomenal consciousness, representational content and cognitive access: A missing link between two debates. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences,14(4), 1021-1035. doi:10.1007/s11097-014-9399-2
Lemonick, M. (2004). Why Do We Dream? Time International,163(10), 44-44.
Nishimoto, S., Vu, A. T., Naselaris, T., Benjamini, Y., Yu, B., & Gallant, J. L. (2011). Reconstructing Visual Experiences from Brain Activity Evoked by Natural Movies. Current Biology,21, 1641-1646. doi:10.1016/j.cub.2011.08.031
Theoretically, Recording Dreams Is Possible...Scientists Are Trying. (2018, March 21). Retrieved from http://blogs.discovermagazine.com/crux/2018/03/21/recording-dreams-scientists/
Whyte, C. (2017). Sleep signature reveals how much we dream. New Scientist,234(3121), 10. doi:10.1016/s0262-4079(17)30707-8
Windt, J. M., & Voss, U. (2018). Spontaneous Thought, Insight, and Control in Lucid Dreams. Oxford Handbooks Online. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780190464745.013.26
Want to cite this post?
Grassler, A. (2018). The Ethics of Dream Recording. The Neuroethics Blog. Retrieved on , from http://www.theneuroethicsblog.com/2018/12/the-ethics-of-dream-recording.html